The Selfish Gene can’t explain aging – but neither can Multi-level Selection

This is the second of two parts on the history of evolutionary theory.  Last week, I discussed the gene-eyed view of evolution that came to dominate evolutionary theory of the 20th century.  In the 1960s, this view hardened into a dogma, and provoked a reaction, in recognition of the many cooperative networks in nature that are difficult to explain in terms of “kin selection,” the only recourse of the Selfish Gene.  In Part Two, below, I continue with the science of multilevel selection (MLS), and talk about why aging is a tough nut to crack.  Clearly the selfish gene paradigm is inadequate to explain aging.  MLS provides a formal test for deciding whether a given trait can evolve via group selection, and according to these criteria, aging should not be able to evolve.  

Where do we go from here?  

What is missing from both systems is ecology.  When species’ interpendence is taken into account, it becomes possible to understand aging and many other cases where individuals sacrifice their own fitness to the community.

 

George Price and D.S. Wilson

We left off last week with kin selection, which is the only source of cooperative behavior that is recognized from the selfish gene perspective.  The science of kin selection was formalized by W. D. Hamilton in 1964 (part 1, part 2).

Just a few years after Hamilton, another young Brit named George Price expanded Hamilton’s rule, using math developed by Fisher himself.  Price’s contribution was to realize that a gene might be shared not just by brothers and cousins, but many distant relatives, and perhaps some unrelated individuals as well.  He read about the controversy surrounding group selection, and he proposed to resolve the question with statistical analysis.  The result was the Price Equation.

Following Fisher’s idea, Price imagined a large population of a single species that remained constant from one generation to the next.  What Price added was to divide the population into cooperative groups.  An altruistic gene, in Price’s model, would give the individual in which it appeared a disadvantage compared to others in that group that might not carry the altruistic gene.  But the group as a whole would thrive in competition with other groups, based on the number of copies of the altruistic gene that appeared in group members.  In other words, a cooperative gene is conceived as increasing the fitness of a group in proportion to how many members of the group have that gene.  This benefits the group in competition with other groups.  However, within each group, some individuals have the gene and others do not.  The individuals who carry the cooperative gene are at a disadvantage relative to selfish individuals within the same group that do not carry the gene.

The Price Equation applies analysis strictly by Fisher’s rules to to this situation, and it measures the balance between individual selection and group selection that can determine the fate of an altruistic gene.

Fig 1a.  This is the model of Fisher.  Genes increase or decrease in frequency over time within a population of fixed total size.

Fig 1b.  This is the model of Price.  Two things are going on simultaneously.  Genes increase or decrease in frequency within each population based on their individual effects.  Meanwhile, some groups are growing at the expense of other groups, based on the aggregate group effects of these same genes.

The form of the Price Equation may be something that only a statistician can love.  But the conclusions are actually quite sensible and intuitive.  In the competition between selfishness and altruism, how do we know which will come out on top?

Group selection prevails, and altruism wins when

  • the cost to the individual is small, and the benefit to the group is large
  • groups are well-segregated with altruists all clumped together in separate groups from non-altruists

Conversely, individual selection prevails, and altruism loses when

  • the cost to the individual is large compared to the benefit to the group
  • groups are integrated, with similar mixtures of altruists and non-altruists in each

The story of Price’s life is wonderfully colorful and tragically fated.  Price did not live to see his ideas spawn a cooperative cult within evolutionary biology, expanding to become a formidable and respected minority in the 21st Century.  It was David Sloan Wilson, a graduate student at Harvard and later a professor at Binghamton, who picked up the Price Equation and built his career promoting and popularizing the idea of group selection, citing hundreds of examples of cooperation in nature that are not well-explained by Hamilton’s Rule, and establishing the plausibility of Price’s model in explaining these.  Wilson promotes the science of multi-level selection (MLS) based on a dynamic balance between evolution operating simultaneously at the level of the individual, and larger communities, groups and ecosystems.

This would seem to be an inclusive position.  Why should it inspire such controversy?  Wilson has been extra-cautious in establishing the scientific basis for multi-level selection.  Nevertheless, he has become a lightning rod for charges that group selection is a fallacious idea, and that the science of MLS somehow lacks legitimacy.  Richard Dawkins, in particular, has become a vituperative antagonist of Wilson’s work.

 

Aging

Aging shows many characteristics that indicate an evolved adaptation – most notably that the genetic basis for aging is hundreds of millions of years old, and seems to have been conserved from microbes to man.  But aging offers no selective advantage to the individual.  In fact, getting old, losing your fertility and dying can only decrease your individual fitness.  So evolution of aging is a prime candidate for explanation in terms of MLS.  Maybe aging evolved because of its benefit to the community.

So it is natural to apply Price’s criteria.  Do we expect group selection or individual selection to predominate in the case of aging?

  • The cost to the individual is high.  (This was the surprising conclusion of a survey of mammals and birds by Daniel Promislow in 1991, and confirmed later by Ricklefs and Bonduriansky with very different methodology.)  Though few animals in the wild drop dead of old age, there are many that begin to lose their competitive edge with age, and they succumb to predators or parasites from which young animals escape.  In other words, individual selection against aging is expected to be very strong.  Strike one.

  • The benefit to the group is hard to measure in the short run.  It comes from maintaining population diversity, and enhancing opportunities for reproduction, so that in the long run the population can evolve faster.  But before we even get to the “long run”, aging has a significant barrier to overcome in the short run, and in the short run, the genetic basis for aging ought to be disappearing more and more from each successive generation.  Strike two.

  • The group that benefits from aging is not well-confined to others that carry the genes for aging.  Far from it.  The only benefit from aging and programmed death is to open a space in the niche, and there is no guarantee that the individual who grows to fill that space will even be of the same species, let alone that it should carry the same gene for aging.  In the SG perspective and the MLS perspective alike, an altruistic trait can evolve only to the extent that the benefits of that trait accrue to others who carry that trait, and this is not the case with aging.  Strike three.

And so, as an explanation for the evolution of aging MLS strikes out.

 

Beyond the Price Equation

The critical omission in the analyses of all three scientists, Fisher, Hamilton and Price, is the volatility of population size, based on interactions among different species.  Population dynamics is the key to understanding why nature provides so many stunning examples of cooperation, and how the “cheater problem” has been avoided.  This was the insight of Michael Gilpin, a mathematical physicist who turned his attention to the problem of group selection in the mid-1970s.  At a time when computer models were already in common use among physicists but not yet among biologists, Gilpin brilliantly exploited the crude computational resources of the day to build a more sophisticated and general model than Fisher or Hamilton or Price.  His 1975 monograph, called Group Selection in Predator- Prey Communities, challenged fundamental assumptions of evolutionary theory, and created a model that is far more consonant with biological reality.  Gilpin’s work remains poorly understood and its significance unappreciated to this day.

The essence of Gilpin’s message was that the best strategy for individual success is to eat more and transform the biomass of your food into your own offspring, which take over the population.  This strategy leads at the individual level to success, and at the group level it leads to rapid population growth.  The catch is that “food” is also biological.  Whatever your species is eating will suffer a decline as you try to eat more and more, and simultaneously your numbers are growing and growing.  As your species prospers, your food species goes into decline.

Here’s the punch line:  Exponential mathematics makes this process rapid and dramatic.  One generation there’s plenty of food, the next generation there is no food at all.  The process of ecosystem collapse is very rapid.  It is a powerful Darwinian force, a fitting counter-balance to the raw strength of selection for selfishness.

(The idea that population regulation is an adaptive biological function, evolved by group selection was not new with Gilpin.  In his introduction, he credits V. C. Wynne-Edwards (1962) and Sir Alexander Carr-Saunders (1925) before him.  But Gilpin put these ideas on a solid mathematical footing, with an explicit mechanism of action.)

If you evolve to maximize your individual fitness, your children will starve.  This insight changes the landscape of evolutionary biology, and remains unappreciated to this day.

And what of the argument that ecosystems are stable and slow to change?  By all appearances they provide a constant biological background in which species may evolve slowly, one at a time.

The answer is that ecosystems are only stable because they are evolved to be stable.  If every individual were behaving selfishly, as Fisher postulated, then stable ecosystems would be an impossibility.  The stable ecosystems that we see only exist because, long ago, individual selection has been balanced by group selection at the level of the entire ecosystem, severely constraining individual selfishness.

 

Implications for Aging and Beyond

Virtually all of evolutionary theory is rooted in a paradigm where you can separate what happens in a single generation, and then think of multi-generation evolution as if it were an iteration of this single-generation process, over and over again.  Another part of the paradigm is that you can think about one trait evolving in one species apart from its effect on other traits and other species.  Not that anyone believes these things are literally true, but it is widely assumed that they are a rough-and-ready first approximation, a good start for a theory that can afford to refine itself later on, at a different level of detail.  This turns out not to be true.  Ecological interactions must be included from the get-go, or we get a very distorted picture of how evolution works.

Aging contributes to taming population dynamics, to slowing the exponential growth, and to softening the inevitable population crashes that follow.  This is not a slow, long-term benefit (like population diversity), but an immediate and powerful force, providing protection against a danger that would otherwise wipe out a species in just a few generations’ time.   It is a powerful and tangible group-level benefit that simply is not captured in the world-view of the Price Equation.

Beyond aging, there are many other coooperative traits for which you might wonder, how could they have evolved “uphill” in the face of strong individual selection against them?  The answer is that the whole system of evolution has evolved to avoid rewarding individuals that exploit resources unsustainably.  This is part of the story of evolution of evolvability.

The way that evolution works is not what we naively imagined in the early 20th Century, but the dynamic of evolution itself has evolved to be far more sophisticated and subtle.

7 thoughts on “The Selfish Gene can’t explain aging – but neither can Multi-level Selection

  1. The most popular evolutionary theories of aging are the “disposable soma” theory and “antagonistic pleiotropy”. The former says that maintenance processes compete with reproduction – and maintenance processes get short-changed since evolution is all about reproduction. The latter points out that genes that have positive effects at young ages and negative effects at old ages will favoured by selection.

    These theories have nothing to do with kin selection or group selection. In both cases, aging is regulated by genes that directly benefit those who possess them – by increasing their reproductive success while young. I don’t think you can get away with saying that senescence can only decrease individual fitnesses. It just isn’t so.

    • Hi, Tim –
      I’m glad to be in touch with you after many years. I remember being intrigued by many things you have explored, including finger yoga.
      Senescence can only decrease fitness, but as you say, popular theories hypothesize that senescence has a hard-wired link to fertility, which increases fitness.
      I don’t believe in the pleiotropic theories because it’s just too easy to separate aging from fertility in genetic experiments. When Michael Rose bred fruit flies for longevity over 25 years time, their fertility increased! I don’t believe in “disposable soma” because it is rooted in the idea that aging is caused by not having enough food energy to repair the body and make babies at the same time. This is belied by everything we know about caloric restriction. I have a detailed response to both theories which you can read here.

      • The files were probably in an unorthodox environment – according to Rose:

        “The result has been the opposite – that the long-lived flies actually lay more eggs at every stage of life. Rose explains this result in terms of an interaction between genotype and environment. The long-lived flies show other weaknesses that would make them poor competitors in the wild, and perhaps these traits are the true areas of antagonistic pleiotropy.”

        Regarding energy restriction, I compare the altered gene expression profile of CR to gambling your last pennies to get your bus fair home.

        Usually gambling doesn’t make much sense. However, if you only have a few pennies, it can pay to gamble them – so at least you can afford the bus home.

        Senescence is the much the same. Maintenance often gets short-changed through being low-priority – except when it’s the only option available – due to lack of resources for other things. Then it pays to gamble whatever resources you have on a chance to live a bit longer – and try again.

        I wrote this up some time ago:

        “Since it is not intuitively obvious how a smaller resource pie can result in some processes getting more of the pie, I sometimes find it useful to explain the phenomenon using an analogy:

        Imagine you are going on a holiday, and have a limited budget to spend. You might typically spend your money relaxing and having a good time. However, imagine also that you have to buy a ticket home again – and then consider the effect of budget cuts. Initially reductions in the budget might result in similar behaviour, but for a shorter duration – you pack your bags and go home earlier. However, consider the effect of budget cuts which mean that you can no longer afford the ticket home. Suddenly what resources you have start getting spent on activities that would not have received attention before. You might wire home for funds. You might try and get a job. Or you might gamble the money in a casino – hoping to increase your funds enough to be able to afford the vital ticket.

        This shift in the recipients of resources that occurs when they are limited is very much like the survival mode which results from dietary energy restriction.”

        • Evolution does not have to reinvent aging, it has been with us since the beginning. Evolution just needs to adjust aging for each species. Let’s imagine we are living in Africa a half million years ago as H. erectus in small tribes scattered around the continent. Occasionally a lion comes into our village to get dinner. Every one runs away. You don’t have to outrun the lion, just outrun the slowest person. It is not survival of the fittest; but rather the death of the slowest. What is the best strategy for evolution? If all the adults are fit, then a child gets eaten each time. Fairly soon there are no children left, the tribe can’t produce the next generation, and eventually even the fittest individual in the tribe gets eaten, and the tribe becomes extinct. However, there are other tribes so life goes on. In another tribe aging has slowed down the old folks, and when the lion comes he eats an elder. The lion has to eat a third of the tribe (the elders) before he starts eating children. meanwhile the tribe keeps producing more children and more adults grow older to feed the lion. This tribe survives and eventually repopulates the village of the extinct tribe. So we have group selection without the
          H. erectus species becoming extinct. The key here is that instead of evolution selecting individuals, it is selecting tribes. Likewise, there could be other forces besides lions driving group selection. Altruism may cost the individual; but if the tribe does not survive, neither will the individual.

  2. “The essence of Gilpin’s message was that the best strategy for individual success is to eat more and transform the biomass of your food into your own offspring, which take over the population. This strategy leads at the individual level to success, and at the group level it leads to rapid population growth. The catch is that “food” is also biological. ”

    I would also add that the fittest organisms would normally be the least likely to die in a population. Without aging the population’s genetic diversity would shrink as their progeny would keep on living indefinitely and out-competing all the lesser members of the group. The already mentioned problem of resource constraint also means that a population carrying genes against aging would in effect be competing with its own progeny. In a given niche the ones most likely to benefit from an opening caused by aging are the progeny of the fittest, since these will tend to outcompete the less fit for the freed resources.

    • Gilpin’s point is that after the “fittest” organism comes to dominate the group, the group becomes the least fit compared to other groups that co-exist sustainably with their food species. Greed pulls the base out from under the ecosystem, and the whole community dies waiting for food species once again to take root.

      • From what I understand there can be booms and busts cycles in some biological systems. http://wps.pearsoncustom.com/wps/media/objects/5697/5834441/ebook/htm/0cc6e.htm?36.06

        So overextent can and does seem to occur. I think it would occur even without the fittest organisms being involved, as usually the fittest is only slightly fitter than the rest of the population. It is likely that some gene that regulates behavior so as to not destroy the niche would propagate more successfully through the population as not only the fittest but the population as a whole can generally destroy or overextend with regards to resources.

        In some invasive species it’s been seen that they some tend to extend massively at the cost of the new ecosystem. One may imagine these species tendencies where kept in check by native predators in their original environment and not by genes to regulate and limit resource use.

        In sum,
        Overextention of a species can occur even if brought about by the average members of a species. But I think the fittest add to the problem, because they may exacerbate the issue, and they will tend to reduce genetic variability especially in a boom and bust cycle where the less fit would tend to be wiped out.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *